Reason value knowledge
An attempt by AI to summarize this article
Living organisms demonstrate their autonomous agency through goal-directed behavior as the objective and ultimate propensity to survive, reproduce, and flourish. Their persistence over many generations has entailed the critical capacity to accumulate and process information as they adapt to their conditions of existence. This is a behavioral orientation that resembles a human perspective, point of view, or set of values, and it is this biological agency that, in the course of evolution, has generated the multitude of organisms, structures, processes, and behaviors that we see in the community of life today – including human subjectivity.
Information capture, storage, processing, and communication = knowledge
Information prioritization that guides behavioral orientation = value
Adaptation = reason
This article is one of a series investigating biological agency and its relationship to human agency. These articles include: What is life? – the crucial role of agency in determining what it is to be alive; Purpose – the semantic link between agency and purpose, and the history of teleology; Biological agency – a description of what it is to be a biological agent; Human-talk – the application of minded and human terms to non-human organisms; Being like-minded – the way our understanding of minded human agency is grounded in mindless biological agency; Biological values – the evolutionary grounding of human values in mindless behavioral orientation, Agency & evolution – the evolutionary development of human agency out of biological agency; Morality – moral naturalism as the grounding of human morality in biological normativity; and plant intelligence as an example of language attempting to capture the reality of biological agency with the use of cognitive metaphor.
For a summary of the findings and claims made in these articles see the key points Epilogue at the end of this article which claims that many of the words we associate with human intentional psychology and human agency become more scientifically coherent when applied more generally in biology; also the narrative summary of claims that is given in the article biological desiderata. Though word meanings cannot be changed at will, in science it is possible to refine categories and concepts to better represent the world.
Introduction
Is there any connection between our subjective capacities to reason, evaluate, and accumulate knowledge and our biological nature? Can biology inform our understanding of these three intellectual pillars of our humanity?
Reason value knowledge: these are foundational concepts in philosophy, psychology, and human life – they comprise a trio of categories with their own academic specialties that we know as epistemology (the theory of knowledge), ethics (the study of value and the principles that govern behavior), and logic (as the principles of reasoning).
The great philosophers of ancient Greece gave these three categories of mental activity pride of place and they have stood the test of time, which suggests that they are not just labels of convenience – they are more like archetypal features of the mind that are embedded in our human nature . . . innate characteristics.
As properties of the mind, these mental attributes are regarded as uniquely human ‘higher’ cognitive faculties. But how are they to be explained: how did they evolve, and could they be related to ‘lower’ biological phenomena?
Functional equivalence
The multiplicity of physical structures we encounter in the community of life evolved under the influence of a limited range of selection pressures. These are the factors that influence the survival, reproduction, adaptation (and therefore evolution) of every organism. Adaptations that enhance an organism’s fit within its habitat improve its chances of survival and reproduction. These are mostly external factors (e.g. predation, competition, disease, environmental change) and the existing structures of the organism will constrain possible evolutionary outcomes.
In this way selection pressure shapes the evolution of life, influencing the traits that become prevalent in populations based on environmental challenges and opportunities. Understanding these pressures illuminates patterns of biodiversity and the convergent pathways that organisms follow when faced by similar ecological challenges.
We understand how bird wings and butterfly wings, though they evolved in different ways, did so because of the advantages afforded by flight. Though, in evolutionary terms, these wings are unrelated, in functional terms they are equivalent – they serve the same functional role.
Across the vast diversity of life, there are common functional uniformities due to shared selection pressures that have shaped organisms in similar ways (convergent evolution, similar physiological mechanisms, niche adaptation).
These principles, while usually applied to physical structures, are equally relevant to mental phenomena. The selection pressures that drove the evolution of human cognition were biologically universal selection pressures that different organisms resolved in different ways.
What, then, are the biological functional equivalents of human cognition?
While recognizing the uniqueness of human subjective experience we can understand cognition in a broader biological sense by, as it were, reducing mental states to their biological functional equivalents – by biologizing psychology.
There is no universally accepted definition of human cognition but definitions refer to the mental processes involved in acquiring knowledge and understanding through thought, experience, and the senses. This encompasses a wide range of processes, including perception, attention, memory, reasoning, problem-solving, and decision-making. This involves the integration of sensory information and the application of prior knowledge to navigate and interpret the environment. It also includes the abilities to think abstractly, understand complex ideas, learn from experience, and adapt behaviors based on new information.
While human cognition has several uniquely defining features, most of its characteristics have functional equivalents in other organisms that perceive, process, and respond to information about their internal and external environments. These include functional equivalents of sensory perception, memory, learning, reason, decision-making, knowledge, value, and other factors that influence the behavior of all organisms through their objective and ultimate propensity to survive, reproduce, adapt, and evolve. These universal functions and purposes are manifest throughout the range of biological structures found in the community of life. They are a critical part of the functional integration of all biological agents.
This mode of cognition does not occur in inanimate matter and, while the physical structures of human cognition (e.g. brains and nerves) did not evolve out of the physical structures of biological cognition (e.g. chemical sensing systems in plants or amoeba ), in functional terms, it is clear that human cognition is a highly evolved form of biological cognition.
Biological cognition
Biological cognition is a universal property of biological agents that has a functional equivalence to human cognition. It includes equivalences of reason, value, knowledge, memory, learning, communication, perception, experience, sentience, even subjectivity, and more. It refers, for example, to the way organisms adaptively interpret and prioritize sensory data, allowing them to perceive and respond to their conditions of existence. It considers how organisms access, store, retrieve, process, prioritize, and communicate information; how they and their parts use various forms of reasoning or problem-solving. Collectively these properties provide the adaptive functionality that integrates organismal proximate and ultimate goals and distinguishes organisms as the primary autonomous biological agents.
Describing goal-directed behavior
The universal goal-directed behavior of organisms is an objective fact and it is this biological agency that distinguishes the living from the inanimate and dead.
This website recognizes human cognitive agency as a limited and highly evolved form of this more general biological agency. Are there different kinds of goal-directed behavior displayed by the world’s organisms and, if so, what words do we use to describe them?
The language of human agency has a rich vocabulary of descriptive terms, mostly those of intentional psychology, like ‘want’, ‘need’, ‘like’, ‘prefer’, ‘interest’, ‘strategy’, ‘goal’, ‘love’, ‘deceive’, ‘consider’, ‘desire’, ‘know’, ‘learn’, ‘remember’, and so on . . . the list is a long one. These words denote human intentions and, significantly, these intentions may be either conscious or unconscious.
We know that all organisms share the universal propensity to survive and reproduce. This means that all organisms share the same general needs although, for humans, these needs are expressed in cognitive form.
All life depends on water if it is to persist. This need for water can be described in cognitive terms as ‘thirst’. However, in biological terms the need for water is biologically universal but we cannot say that a plant is ‘thirsty’ because ‘thirsty’ is a strictly human word that implies a cognitive process. So what word do we use to describe the ‘thirst’ of a plant?
There is no vocabulary for the many different kinds of pre-cognitive agency, and so we resort to the rich vocabulary of human intentional psychology that describes cognitive human agency in all its differentiated variety.
An intuitive taxonomy of this minded vocabulary (the language of intentional psychology) reveals three word clusters. The conceptual focus of these three clusters expresses the core ways in which human minded agency is differentiated from its grounding biological agency. That is, the language of human intentional psychology revolves around the three central ideas of reason, knowledge, and value.
This might, at first, appear an arbitrary and personal selection of categories, but it is one reinforced both by superficial and more in -depth examination, and its emphasis in many areas of human life, not least of which is the long-standing philosophical distinction between logic, epistemology, and ethics.
It is also supported by the preconditions necessary for the biological axiom to apply. It is the information (knowledge) contained in DNA, subjected to environmental feedback (reason), on a (behaviourally orientated i.e. evaluating) agent, that makes life possible. Thus, in the course of evolution mindless information, subjected to environmental feedback in goal-directed individuals has become differentiated into minded knowledge, reason, and value (also present mindlessly in minded organisms).
Reason – vocabulary would include: ‘deliberation’, ‘consideration’, ‘strategy’, ‘plan’, ‘calculation’.
Knowledge – vocabulary would include: ‘knowing’, ‘learning’, ‘remembering’, ‘recognizing’.
Value – vocabulary would include: ‘want’, ‘prefer’, ‘like’, ‘attract’, ‘need’
These three core aspects of human agency are like the minded and differentiated evolutionary developments of less differentiated (more generalized, primitive, or ancestral) and grounding biological agency.
If we want to understand human agency – what is needed for humans to function in a uniquely human way – then we must look beyond consciousness to these three elements of our mindedness. Reason, knowledge, and value are our most informative general summary concepts for human agency.
To comprehend human agency in an evolutionary sense we must understand both its relationship to other forms of biological agency – through the grounding characteristics expressed in the biological axiom – but also its uniquely defining and refined emergent minded characteristics of reason, knowledge, and value.
Of necessity, the human capacity to reason, evaluate, and accumulate knowledge evolved out of the more generalized shared goals of the biological axiom? But what form do these concepts take when linked to mindless nature?
This needs closer scrutiny.
A closer glimpse of links to biological agency comes with the realization that purpose, reason, knowledge, value, and agency can be present in humans in unconscious forms: they are not necessarily related to conscious minds.
Cognitive evolution
It seems intuitively obvious that questions about cognition cannot go back further in evolutionary time than the origin of brains and nerves, while ‘higher’ cognitive faculties, like this trio of reasoning, valuing, and knowing must be linked even more strictly to the conscious mental activity of Homo sapiens.
Current speculation about the evolution of cognition[2] engages discussion about a possible ‘cognitive revolution’ about 300,000 years ago (various other dates have been suggested), the use of symbolic and recursive thinking, creative imagination, abstract thought, sociality, the development of language, the use of foresight and hindsight, and other mental faculties that we assume are largely confined to our own species. The assumption is that these mental properties emerged when the mammalian brain attained the particular degree of organic complexity and organization that is only found in humans.
This is the mainstream biological view. But could uniquely human mental faculties, as a matter of biological necessity, also bring along some evolutionary baggage – echoes of evolutionary history – some grounding properties that are shared with the broader community of life?
This article investigates human minded agency as a highly evolved form of mindless biological agency. It suggests that mental faculties we conventionally regard as uniquely human are highly evolved evolutionary characteristics that are built on a biological bedrock that reaches back to the origins of life.
Similarity & difference
Organisms are products of evolution, and to understand any organism (or, for that matter, its structures, processes, and behaviors) in evolutionary terms requires a knowledge of not only those characteristics that make the organism or feature unique, but also the additional necessarily associated characteristics that indicate evolutionary relationships – characteristics that are shared with other organisms.
The unique characteristics we use to identify particular organisms and define biological features are theoretical points of distinction but they do not exist in the world in isolation – they bring along with them evolutionary baggage as additional characteristics that are shared with other organisms. In the real world uniquely defining features are combined with features that are shared with other organisms as a result of common ancestry. It is this combination of similarity and difference (shared and unique characteristics) that makes it possible to establish evolutionary relationships.
The simultaneous manifestation of similarities and differences when comparing organisms and their structures can be both counterintuitive and confusing but it is cleverly captured in the scientific system of binomial nomenclature. While Homo sapiens is a unique species, the genus name Homo establishes its broad evolutionary context of shared characteristics – the ‘family resemblance’ that facilitates comparison. The specific epithet, sapiens, added to the genus name indicates difference by designating what is unique. The significance of this quirk of evolutionary biology will become obvious shortly.
Novelty emerges from the evolutionary process in a graduated way because it is built on, and limited by, its antecedent conditions. Think of, say, diagrams of the evolving horse or human, and the different structures (fins, wings, arms & legs) that all have a pentadactyl ground plan.
We accept as uncontroversial the fact that we can, for example, provide a uniquely defining description of the human heart while at the same time considering features of the human heart that are shared with other species. But, transposing these ideas to the realm of mental attributes attracts a barrage of philosophical, methodological, and cultural resistance.
Why, say, can’t ‘reason’ exist in nature in this way – in a uniquely human form that also shares some properties with other species?
The answer seems simple and straightforward. Reason is a useful concept precisely because it excludes other species, because it is a uniquely human mental capacity – that is what we mean by ‘reason’.
But, while we don’t talk about the ‘arms’ of whales, we are prepared to make an evolutionary scientific comparison between our arms and the fins of whales: we recognize that there is a real biological relationship between the two.
However, to make a similar claim for ‘reason’ seems preposterous. Reason is so deeply embedded in our cultural tradition as a ‘minded’ concept that any suggestion otherwise is soon denied or ignored.
It is obvious that we are never going to accept, seriously, any talk of, say, ‘plant reason’ other than as metaphor. But could there be some scientific truth in the claim that human reason has evolutionary antecedents in other organisms? We know that our inherited color vision, body structures, even our fear of spiders and snakes, pre-date the emergence of Homo sapiens in evolutionary time. Why can’t reason have some evolutionary baggage?
Let’s look more closely at our scientific understanding of ‘reason’ in the broad context of evolution, beginning with those characteristics that all living organisms have in common.
Agency
What is it that makes life special and different . . . how do we distinguish life from non-life?
An answer to the question ‘What is life?‘ seems a long way off, but this website claims that the simplest and most obvious characteristic of life – what distinguishes living organisms from inanimate objects like rocks – is its agency.
Living organisms are autonomous biological agents acting on, and responding to, their conditions of existence. They display flexible goal-directed behavior and their structures, processes, and behaviors function in support of the propensity of the organism, as a whole, to survive, reproduce, and flourish. These biological goals are objective, universal, and ultimate: objective because they are a mind-independent fact; universal because they are expressed by all living organisms (in the sense that they are the necessary preconditions for life); and ultimate because they are a summation of all proximate goals. Without a behavioral disposition, the notions of goal-directed behavior and agency are incoherent.
Biological agency is not a metaphor, nor is it ‘agent-like’ . . . and it is not just a convenient way of representing life – a useful heuristic. These biological goals are real, and they endow all living organisms with real agency. Human minded agency did not invent biological agency as a convenient metaphor or figurative creation; real biological agency made human subjectivity and human agency possible.
If you accept that the word ‘agency’, as outlined above, is being used in a scientifically and semantically legitimate way, then you might be surprised by a necessary but perhaps unexpected consequence . . . that agency can be expressed by mindless organisms.
It was this mindless agency, operating through evolution for about 3.5 billion years, that eventually produced human subjectivity as just one species-specific expression of biological agency. In other words, human agency is biological agency as expressed in a uniquely minded human form. Real biological agency ‘created’ human minded agency: human agency did not invent biological agency as a mental metaphor.
Universal conditions of biological agency
Each species expresses the universal conditions of biological agency (survival, reproduction, flourishing) through its own particular combination of structures, processes, and behaviors. Some of these characteristics are species-specific and therefore unique, while others are shared with other organisms as a result of common ancestry.
While the agency of an organism is expressed through the actions performed by structures and processes, it is the universal conditions of agency that establish the limits and ends of processes: it is the goals that are prior. Structures evolve in response to the requirements of agential goals and, in this sense, action and process precede structure (constrain structural possibilities). Many different structures (the world’s organisms past and present) can satisfy the same universal agential conditions, but it is the goals that ultimately determine and limit the structures engaged.
This is sometimes treated as being problematically teleological.
What are biological goals?
The goals of organisms are the uncomplicated limits or ends to natural processes that follow conventional causal pathways. Having goals does not require or imply the presence of supernatural forces, the reading of human intentions into nature, or backward causation acting like a mysterious pull from the future; nor are they just a convenient heuristic device.
Only when the goals of whole organisms are known can their necessitating conditions be understood. Thus, biological ends have explanatory priority (hence the ‘final cause’ associated with teleology) but they do not challenge the natural order of cause and effect: they are first in explanation, and last in causation.
Biological goals are real in nature (open to empirical investigation). Teleological explanations are therefore a feature of biology that distinguishes it from physics, chemistry, and explanations of the inanimate world. It is also why, for example, it makes sense to ask what biological structures, processes, and behaviors are ‘for’, while not asking the same question of rocks and the moon.
Behavioral orientation
Having goals entails a behavioral orientation that makes some outcomes more probable than others. This gives biological agency a ‘direction’ that in human terms would be called an ‘attitude’, ‘perspective’, or ‘point of view’.
In its highly evolved and human minded form goal-directed behavior is treated as an expression of value. This is what underpins but does not determine, moral behavior (see biological values).
Evolutionary selection pressure depends on the effectiveness of structures, processes, and behaviors in attaining the universal goals of biological agency.
Universal traits of biological agency
Is it possible to establish the universal traits that are necessary for the universal goals of the biological axiom to be attained?
Selection pressure, in evolutionary biology, refers to the factors that determine which individuals within a population are more likely to survive, reproduce, and flourish. This is natural selection as a process that leads to the adaptation and evolution of species over time.
The biological concepts of adaptation, natural selection, and fitness maximization relate to the necessary conditions of biological agency. Without the presumption of agency, these ideas become incoherent since they infer that conditions of existence can facilitate or impede the attainment of real goals – whether these goals are minded or mindless.
Adaptation, as a mindless process, is neither deliberate nor conscious but it is goal-directed and therefore agential. Furthermore, all biological structures, processes, and behaviors are subordinate to the universal, objective, and ultimate conditions that constitute the unity of purpose for every living organism.
Life is therefore more about processes than structures. Universal goals are attained by means of universal agential traits that are the preconditions for biological agency.
These critical agential traits have never been formalized in biological science because we do not willingly regard organisms as agents. These traits – the underlying agential traits that all organisms must possess – can be determined, not by experiment, but as a matter of biological necessity.
These are not the goals themselves, as stated in the biological axiom, but the essential biological agential ingredients needed to achieve these goals . . . the basic principles of biological agency.
This article and the article discussing biological agency refer to the following conditions:
. the demonstration of agency through behavioral autonomy – the capacity to act on, and respond to, the conditions of existence in an individually flexible way
. the capacity to act in a manner that facilitates the attainment of goals (the capacity for adaptation (‘self-correction’)
. the demonstration of a specific behavioral disposition (orientation or perspective) – as the propensity to survive, reproduce, and flourish (biological axiom)
. the capacity to store, retrieve, process, and exchange, information
Though these conditions may be formulated in various ways, we intuitively recognize these universal traits as core characteristics that we humans share with all other organisms.
Humans, as biological agents, must share with all other organisms these universal traits of agency. However, as highly evolved organisms they are expressed not only in this biological grounding but also in its highly evolved and differentiated minded form that is also represented in language. The four conditions listed above are (more or less) represented in human language as ‘self’, ‘reason’, ‘value’, and ‘knowledge’. However, human language has differentiated these core ingredients to include related ideas like ‘communication’, ‘learning’, ‘memory’, ‘consciousness’, ‘cognition’, ‘intelligence’, ‘problem-solving’, and so on.
It is not coincidental that the essential general traits of biological agency listed above correlate with the human cognitive traits of knowledge (information, epistemology), reason (self-correction, adaptation, logic), and value (behavioral disposition, orientation, or mental perspective).[1]
Human agency evolved out of biological agency and therefore shares many of its grounding characteristics.
Expressing agency
Each species of organism, as a matter of biological necessity, expresses biological agency using the means at its disposal – that is, by using the structures, processes, and behaviors bequeathed to it by its evolutionary history. We dismiss biological agency as instinctive, reactive, mechanical, and devoid of cognitive processing in contrast with human agency which uses foresight, symbolism, abstraction, cultural interaction, and ethical decision-making. In so doing we ignore the universal goals and conditions that humans and other organisms have in common.
Humans can use their minds as agential tools to help them achieve their universal biological goals: but minds and brains are just an evolutionary feature, or tool, like any other. Birds use their acute sight to help attain universal biological goals while fish use their capacity to live underwater, and oak trees use their own unique structures, processes, and behaviors to achieve the same universal ends.
Our human mental motivation – the source of the agency that drives our behavior – can be reduced to three key elements.
. Our biological needs and desires (will or appetite) simplified under the heading of values.
. What we know (knowledge) – what we understand about our conditions of existence – our beliefs.
. The facility to respond flexibly, to adapt, and to self-correct by using our reason.
Human history is, in a strong sense, a testament to the interaction between the core mental faculties of values, beliefs, and reason.
While it is clear that human values have a strong and inherited biological component, what about reason and knowledge?
We can trace the evolutionary antecedents of physical structures to their, mostly, simpler origins. But does it make sense to look for the evolutionary precursors of these major minded characteristics of human agency? Could these, like physical structures, be present in nature by degree? How could an oak tree possibly demonstrate knowledge, or values – surely that is nonsense?
Perhaps biological agency, and its uniquely human modes of expression, are like sexuality. We accept that sexuality exists almost universally across the community of life, even though it is expressed in a diversity of behaviours and physical forms. Simply because human sexuality is expressed in a uniquely human way does not mean that only human sexuality is real, and that the sexuality of other organisms is only sexual-like. An oak tree expresses value through the physical and behavioural means of its own unique form of agency. This is nothing like human value, but it is connected to human value through the shared characteristics of biological agency.
Such a proposal triggers a cognitive dissonance because we can both confuse (fail to distinguish between) and conflate (treat as being the same) the universal, objective, and ultimate values of biological agency, and the uniquely minded values and goals of human agency.
We both confuse (fail to distinguish between) and conflate (treat as being the same) the universal and objective ultimate values of biological agency, and the uniquely minded values and goals of human agency.
Since there is no technical terminology to describe the expression of biological values we fall back on the human vocabulary of intentional psychology. And, since many organisms do not have minds, this human-talk (anthropomorphic language) is understandably dismissed as cognitive metaphor – which ignores its evolutionary grounding in biological agency. We make a clear
In other words, we mistakenly presume that biological agency must be minded agency, like human agency – that mindedness is a precondition for agency in living organisms. It is probably for this reason that we mistakenly infer that the unreality associated with the application of minded language to mindless organisms (cognitive metaphor) translates comfortably into the unreality of biological agency. That is, we conflate the simple distinction between the minded and the mindless with the complex distinction between biological agency and human agency. It is not that biological agency is a subjective creation of the human mind (cognitive metaphor or heuristic), rather that the proximate and uniquely minded goals of human agency evolved out of, and share characteristics with, the universal, objective, and ultimate mindless goals of biological agency.
The evolution of inherent purpose in mindless organisms created minds: minds did not create purpose.
Human agency is described using the language of intentional psychology but there is no technical terminology to describe biological values. Biological values are therefore described using the language of intentional psychology, which is therefore reasonably dismissed as cognitive metaphor – that mindedness is a precondition for agency in living organisms. Thus, we conflate the simple distinction between the minded and the mindless with the complex distinction between biological agency and human agency. It is not that biological agency is a subjective creation of the human mind (cognitive metaphor or heuristic), rather that the proximate and uniquely minded goals of human agency evolved out of, and share characteristics with, the universal, objective, and ultimate mindless goals of biological agency. The inherent purpose expressed by the goal-directed behaviour of mindless organisms created minds: minds did not create purpose.
Philosophical context
This website argues that biological agency is not a subjective human creation – a convenient fiction or metaphor – instead it is part of the empirical fabric of the world.
While human conscious intention is clearly different from mindless and mechanical genetically determined goal-directed behavior it is, nevertheless, a product (an evolutionary development of) the same universal biological agency.
The characteristics that we believe most closely define our human nature – our mental capacity to reason, value, and know – evolved out of the universal antecedent agential characteristics of living organisms.
We recognize biological agency in the autonomous and flexible goal-directed (purposive) behaviour that is displayed by all living organisms as they act on and respond to their conditions of existence. Organisms are not passive like rocks. We see agency in the orientation of leaves towards the sun, a fish darting from a predator, humans shopping in a supermarket. Goal-directed behaviour is a universal, ultimate, and objective characteristic of living organisms.
Only humans (and possibly other sentient animals) are consciously aware of this agential and purposive behaviour, and certainly only humans can represent it in words. But that does not mean that agency and purpose only exist in human minds – that they are a creation of human minds.
Living organisms are agents, they are not merely agent-like. The fact that most do not have minds does not somehow dissolve their agency. What does make human agency unique is its capacity to use language as a way to describe inner states.
The behavior of all organisms is a consequence of inner processing but only humans use words to describe their inner states – which they do using the language of intentional psychology.
What more can be said about this strange connection between mindless biological agency and the biological agency that is expressed by humans in minded terms?
Human behavior & human nature
When investigating the difference between biological agency and biological agency in its minded human form, we are confronted by the problem of human nature.
There are a surprisingly large number of answers to the question ‘What is it that makes us uniquely human?‘ Answers to this difficult question can come from many disciplines but, for the biologist, the answer must engage our evolution because we are ‘the way that nature made us’ and, while we emphasize our uniqueness and difference, there is much that unites us with the community of life.
Before considering our unique mental characteristics an abbreviated list of physical characteristics can set the scene, they include: blushing; the smiling and laughing associated with a sense of humour; having little body hair; large brains relative to other animals (1200-1400 cc) which require supporting muscles, a protective cranium, and high energy use (25% total); bipedal gait with improved vision and hands freed for tools (but resulting in back problems and narrowing of the hips and birth canal) with more deaths in childbirth than other primates resulting in premature birth and soft skull; children dependent on parents for longer hence a prolonged period of learning and socialization; opposable thumbs (thumbs can touch ring and little fingers facilitating use of tools; a descended larynx, originating c. 350, 000 BP and probably related to speech and language; living beyond reproductive age; use of fire, notably for cooking foods.
Cognitive psychologist Steven Pinker, who has dedicated his life’s work to the study of human nature, provides a definition of the mental aspects of our human nature as the innate abilities and predispositions as, ‘the totality of our universal patterns of thought, feeling, and behaviour‘ (The Blank Slate), and on his website as ‘ . . . the sum of the innate or potential behaviors and mechanisms in the mind that are typical of the human species, arising from the interaction of the genome and the environment over evolutionary time’.
The set of evolved psychological traits and capacities that are universal to the human species include: language; a capacity for social interaction and cooperation; emotions, and various other cognitive abilities. Evolutionary psychology, Pinker points out ‘ . . . has documented hundreds of universals that cut across the world’s cultures . . .’ Included in the list of universal human psychological traits must be those universal biological characteristics out of which these psychological traits evolved and on which they depend. Unique human psychological traits are necessarily biologically inseparable from their shared evolutionary baggage, the universal characteristics of biological agency. Pinker himself points out that ‘ . . . many psychological traits (such as our taste for fatty foods, social status, and risky sexual liaisons) are better adapted to the evolutionary demands of an ancestral environment . . .‘.
Features we associate with human mental capacity include: social cooperation that extends beyond our own relatives; the use of language to communicate information; a highly developed capacity to explain, predict, control and make use of complex technology. One way of expressing this is to point out that only humans use culture as a form of cumulative collective learning that has developed synergistically with other mental attributes incorporated in spoken, to written, printed, and electronic forms. We have a creative intelligence that allows us to reflect and communicate not only about the past and future, but also abstract ideas that engage reflexive and recursive thought. Our use of reason gives us a unique rationality that can override our intuitive behaviour as codes of behaviour (morality).
We can list and separate universal human psychological traits into a convenient theoretical package, but in practice – in reality – this package is inextricably locked inside the much larger evolutionary bag of universal biological agency.
We assess agency primarily by behavior, even among humans who can communicate their inner states through language (actions speak louder than words). We are familiar with our own inner states and the language that is used to describe them but we know little about the inner states of other species although we know that they must exist. Our denial of biological agency is an acute form of anthropocentrism.
We humans are selves with knowledge, values, and the capacity to self-correct. Our behavior – in so far as we can reduce it to simple terms – is a product of the interaction between our reason, beliefs, desires, and our conditions of existence. This is what makes us tick. But because other species do not have the same (mental) internal drivers of behavior as us humans does not mean that they have no internal drivers.
All living organisms demonstrate the universal traits of biological agency: autonomy, information processing, behavioral orientation, and adaptation. Human agency is just one evolutionary (minded) manifestation of a more general and universal biological agency.
Internal processes
Let’s put humans aside for one moment.
We assign agency to an object or organism because of its behavior. We, and other organisms, would treat a rock behaving like an animal as a biological agent.
Though we judge agency by behavior, we know that the source of the behavior – what powers behavior, gives an organism its motivation, drive, or vitality – arises internally. Though the stimulus for activity may be external to the organism, all behavior – as the response of a biological agent to its conditions of existence – is a consequence of internal processing.
Biologically we know that internal processing – like all structures processes and behaviors in living organisms – has an ultimate unity of purpose . . . the goals of biological agency which are the necessary preconditions for life.
The multiplicity of structures, processes, and behaviors that we see in the community of life – the different ways of processing information and adapting – are simply different solutions that use the same behavioral orientation to in the face of the same problem of existence. Humans are no exception.
Returning to humans.
From this universal biological perspective, human internal processing is just one of nature’s many ways of addressing the problem of existence. The brain is just one highly evolved organ facilitating the attainment of the goals of biological agency.
However, this situation is complicated by several factors. Firstly, we are humans and therefore take a special interest in our own internal processing. Second, we have the capacity for language and can therefore communicate with one another about our internal states directly, rather than through the medium of behavior (although speech is a form of behavior).
Though the power of the brain has allowed us to pursue goals and ambitions loftier than those of the biological axiom, the goals of our biological agency remain a minimum necessary requirement for life itself. All organisms demonstrate internal processes that motivate their behavior towards the same universal, objective, and ultimate ends.
The fact that one segment of human internal processing is both conscious and intentional, is insignificant in principle, though critical in practice.
There are many ways to measure the ‘success’ of an organism, but the ultimate biological test, the test of life itself, is the degree to which a species or group has shown the capacity to survive, reproduce, or flourish. If sheer biomass is a significant measure then plants, which make up 82% of global biomass, win hands down.[3,4]
This forces us to consider the possibility that, in confronting the problem of existence, plants have been highly successful. And we know that, for this to be the case, their internal processing must also have been extremely effective.
Human-talk
The article on human-talk discussed the various reasons why we use anthropomorphic language. Does human-talk provide any insights into the relationship between biological agency and human agency and the core universal biological traits of information processing, adapting, and behavioral orientation?
The use of the language of cognitive psychology to describe non-mentalistic phenomena is contentious because there are no uncontroversial rules about word usage. If we say, for example, that ‘the heart wants to pump blood‘ we are clearly being anthropomorphic. The heart cannot possibly ‘want’ things in the way that we ‘want’ things; so this is blatant as if metaphor. But when we say ‘the purpose of the heart is to pump blood‘ though you might still regard this as metaphor, the conceptual association with human conscious minds is not so clear-cut.
There are many examples like this. We might accept that an animal, like a unicellular paramecium, with light sensitivity can ‘see’, in a loose sense, but not in the same way that we do . . . it can only ever be as if the paramecium and plants ‘see’ because the plant has no nervous system or eyes.
Viewed through the prism of our consciousness, we humans seem very different from non-sentient organisms. But in a more general sense we have much in common.
Today’s living organisms have persisted in evolutionary time by developing structural and functional adaptations to their historical surroundings. From this biological perspective consciousness is just another functional adaptation, albeit a very effective one.
Consciousness-talk is a specialist vocabulary within a more wide-ranging language that encompasses the general interactions that occur between all organisms and their surroundings. Explanations of the inanimate tend to answer the question ‘How does it work?’ while mindless biological agency prompts the question ‘What is it for?’ When talking about sentient animals we ask ‘How does it feel?’, and when considering human mental events we ask ‘What was the intention?’
All organisms demonstrate, through their behavior, the universal goals of the biological axiom which they express in their real and universal agential traits of information processing, adaptation, and behavioral orientation. The fact that only humans have the language that allows them to describe, share, and critically reflect on their own internal states does not mean that only humans have these internal states.
Of course, the physical manifestation of information processing, adaptation, and behavioral orientation in nature is different depending on the variety of species-specific structures, processes, and behaviors employed.
The goals of biological agency, which are universal and mind-independent, are expressed by means of physical structures, processes, and behaviors that are evolutionarily graded in complexity. We do not have an agential vocabulary that captures this evolutionary gradation. Instead, we have adopted anthropomorphic words that are, by convention, of greater and lesser acceptability in scientific discourse. Human-talk (anthropomorphism) is our best attempt (what we use in desperation) to capture the reality of mindless agency.
There are several reasons why we use human-talk:
. anthropocentric cognitive bias
. genuine metaphor
. lack of appropriate vocabulary
. absence of convincing referents (e.g. not knowing the consciousness of a fish, or reasoning of an owl).
Without adequate vocabulary we inevitably revert to human-talk, which generates semantic and conceptual confusion, and scientific imprecision.
Human-talk will not go away, even in science, because (mostly) it attempts to represent similarities that exist in nature, not just in human minds.
Conceptual gradualism
In the course of cosmic evolution, physical structures, including their properties and relations, increased in number and complexity. This was a process of emergence as everything evolved from a point source. A fundamental change occurred with the emergence of life when the same universal, objective, and ultimate goals and agential traits of biological agency were manifest in an increasingly diverse range of structures, processes, and behaviors as evolution generated (mostly) increasing complexity.
One of the best examples of gradation in a mental attribute is that of consciousness. Not long ago the idea of consciousness extending beyond humans would have been considered ridiculous, if not, blasphemous. Today we have adjusted to the idea of evolutionary gradation and many scientists would be prepared to acknowledge consciousness as existing in lowly organisms – perhaps any organisms with central nervous systems, however simple.
On this understanding, consciousness exists in nature not as present in humans, and absent in all other organisms – but as present in a range of organisms in graduated form – by degree.
This raises a question about semantics and science. We could, for example, be living in a time when the everyday usage and meaning of ‘consciousness’ relates strictly to humans, while the scientific understanding extends to other organisms.
This website argues that the conceptual gradation we now associate with ‘consciousness’ is applicable to other concepts once regarded as restricted to human intentional psychology. These include ‘purpose’, ‘reason’, ‘knowing’, ‘remembering’, ‘intelligence’, ‘learning’, and ‘evaluation’. While common usage might suggest that all these concepts are strictly minded properties, there is a scientific sense in which they are part of the real graduated fabric of biological agency.
If we accept this scientific claim, then we are left with a problem of scientific terms. Do we accept that the word ‘consciousness’ is as appropriately applied to the worm CNS as to the human brain – or do we develop a new terminology? This is all rather complicated so, in practice, we resort to our familiar use of human mental terms and, in effect, deny biological agency by referring to this language as ‘metaphor’.
Rather than acknowledging the universal evolutionarily shared real attributes of biological agency we use ‘as if’ language that denies their existence. This is a strange inversion of reasoning that has caused untold biological damage as we conflate non-human agency with non-existent agency. By dismissing agential similarities in this way, we are not just diminishing their significance, we are denying their reality.
Intentionality
When we understand the way that causal chains proceed we talk about ‘reasons’. So, for example, if we understand the scientific context of the moon orbiting the Earth, we say that there are reasons why this is so. For simplicity, we might call this kind of reason a ‘natural reason’.
We often choose a different terminology when talking about the actions of living organisms. It seems that this is partly because reasons in nature can confer what we construe as benefit. Rather than saying the ‘reason’ for eyes is to see, we say that the ‘purpose’ of eyes is to see. That is, we understand organisms as agents whose goals can be helped or hindered and that is why we don’t say that the ‘purpose’ of the Moon is to orbit the Earth. We recognize that the reason birds have wings is to fly, we have eyes to see, and our hearts pump blood – in all these cases the semantically appropriate word is ‘purpose’ rather than ‘reason’.
But science is still uneasy about ‘purpose’ in nature.
It is conventional to speak of examples, like those given above, as functional adaptations and to restrict the word ‘purpose’ to instances of human intention with ‘purpose’ reserved for ‘minded’ occasions.
Like natural reasons, functional reasons (as purposes) are not metaphorical purposes (the reading of subjective human intention into nature) but functional reasons locked into the genetic and biological character of all organisms.
This illustrates the problems that arise when real but mindless agency is ignored or denied and the complications that arise when trying to find a solution. This is essentially the confusion that results from the fact that human minded agency is a specialized form of mindless biological agency – a factor that complicates the distinction between minded and mindless agency.
One possible way of simplifying, but not solving, this situation is to describe mindless agency as pre-conscious agency.
The mentalistic classification into non-conscious, pre-conscious, and conscious categories suggests that words like ‘intention’, ‘purpose’, ‘adaptation’, ‘selection’, ‘function’, and ‘design’ are sometimes used in relation to pre-conscious functions and sometimes to conscious intentions, hence their ambiguity and resulting semantic demarcation disputes.
The correlations information/knowledge, behavioral disposition/value, and adaptation/reason seem unlikely. What could possibly be the real-world connection between mental states and the mindless behavior of non-human organisms? All we know for sure is that human bodies and brains evolved out of their evolutionary antecedents.
It is now time to consider each of these cases in more detail.
Adaptation (reason)
For any agent to address goals there is a requirement for behavioral flexibility as the capacity to distinguish between those circumstances that can facilitate or impede (help or hinder) the attainment of goals. Expressed in simple terms an agent must have the ability to self-correct or adjust in relation to changing internal and external conditions (the conditions of existence) and in biological science this flexible behavior is generally known as adaptation. This is expressed in human minded terms as the capacity make choices, have preferences, and make decisions.
As already pointed out, this is a universal and critical condition for all organisms (a precondition for life) since without it life would soon cease.
With a universal requirement for each autonomous organism to ‘self-correct’ the actual method by which this is achieved is unimportant, although its efficiency certainly will. Part of the human means of self-correction (there are many other means) is the mental process of reasoning.
Though we place great emphasis on human reason, its biological significance lies in how efficiently it facilitates the attainment of goals. Though reason, by and large, appears to have advanced the human cause, it can be used to advance any ends.
The close link between knowledge, value, reason/information, behavioral orientation, adaptation is evident in a recent definition of reason and rationality by prominent intellectual Steven Pinker, as
‘ . . . the ability to use knowledge to attain goals‘ (Rationality, 2021, p. 36)
This sentence neatly implies not only information as a more generalized form of knowledge, but the behavioral orientation that is a necessary part of any goal-directed behavior.
Universal goals are, of course, achieved by many different but graded means as organisms have, in general over evolutionary time, become more complex, conscious, and comprehending. As a philosopher, Dan Dennett has pointed out, pre-conscious (mindless) goal-directed behavior makes organisms ‘competent without comprehension’.
But, surely, conscious human intentions and deliberations are very different from the genetically-bound mechanical behavior of mindless organisms?
Reason representers
We humans are able to represent, in our minds, the reasons for events and behaviors. We can also talk to one another about them by using symbolic languages. That is, we are reason representers.
It is important to acknowledge that reasons pre-dated reason-representation. There are reasons why the moon orbits the Earth and why spiders build webs, even though the Moon and spiders have neither human-like consciousness or spoken language. The reasons why cacti have spines (their purpose) existed long before human consciousness emerged in evolutionary time.
The fact that only humans can consciously represent reasons and purposes in language and in their minds does not mean that reasons and purposes only exist in human minds – that the reasons and purposes we see in nature are created by our minds – that they are merely metaphors.
Behavioral disposition (value)
The relationship between the universal behavioral disposition of all living organisms and human values and ethical decisions is discussed in detail in the article on biological values.
Autonomous biological agents demonstrate their autonomy by behaving in a particular way. Their behavior is not arbitrary or random, it has a particular orientation, propensity, tendency, or direction. It is as though, as expressed in human terms, they have a particular ‘attitude’, ‘perspective’, or ‘point of view’ in relation to their conditions of existence. This ‘point of view’ is the universal, objective, and ultimate mindless propensity to survive, reproduce, and flourish.
These foundational biological goals, being universal, are shared by humans, but humans express them in a highly evolved and minded form. Manifest in this minded form we call them ‘values’ but in their mindless or pre-cognitive form they are treated as mindless objective behavior. It is this minded behavioral disposition, moderated by reason, that underpins human morality.
Since this behavioral orientation in non-human organisms eventually gave rise, evolutionarily, to value-driven human agency it requires some recognition in biological science. The solution suggested on this website is that the evolutionary connection be acknowledged through the expressions ‘biological values’ or ‘pre-cognitive values’.
For many the clash of the combination of the concepts ‘mindless’ and ‘values’ will be too much to accept. But the facts of biological agency cannot go scientifically unrecognized. The words we associate with human intentional psychology and human agency become more scientifically coherent when applied more generally in biology. Though word meanings cannot be changed at will, in science it is possible to refine categories and concepts to better represent the world.
Information processing (knowledge)
We generally understand stimuli in simple physical terms – the prick of a needle, a sudden sound, the sight of a spider. And we tend to think of this as stimulating our brain to send out electrical signals to parts of our body that then respond accordingly. However, it can be more insightful, scientifically, to reduce this complexity to simpler terms by treating what is going on as information processing.
The regulation of organic processes into flexible behavior with a unity of purpose is a complex process, even on the smallest organic scale. If an organism is to attain goals then its parts must be highly coordinated in their behavior.
Though organisms express a high degree of autonomy they are still part of the continuum of the universe. Agency, as part of their nature, entails a constant process of adjustment (short- and long-term adaptation) in relation to the internal and external circumstances that constitute their conditions of existence. Behavior is therefore a consequence of both internal and external stimuli that have been subjected to internal processing.
This entails information processing on a scale that includes: reception, storage, retrieval, communication/transmission, and translation. These are crucial biological processes with universal functions that have evolved in many different ways.
Reception
Before information can be coordinated it must be received. We asssociate the reception of information with internal and external sensory systems of varying evolutionary complexity.
Each organism exists in its own umweldt (those conditions that are limiting in relation to the attainment of goals given the life-form of the organism and its ecological niche). Among the many commonly encountered factors that can be significant are: light, sound, chemicals, temperature, and other organisms. The complexity of information receivers varies enormously. Protozoans have simple light receptors while humans have complex eyes.
Storage
Information becomes especially valuable if it can be stored ready for future use. We think immediately of the storage of memories and information in human brains but there are more generalized mechanisms available in biology, most notably the information that is encoded in DNA. Every organism is the outcome of a mindless ‘learning’ process that goes back to the dawn of life: it is a consequence of what ‘worked’ in evolutionary time.
Information is stored in processes, structures, and learned behavioral patterns that depend on the organism’s evolutionary history. Perhaps the most obvious is the genetic information of DNA which in the sequence of nucleotide base pairs encodes the instructions for the development, functioning, and reproduction but RNA has a crucial role in gene expression and protein synthesis with messenger RNA (mRNA), transfer RNA (tRNA), and ribosomal RNA (rRNA) storing and transmitting genetic information in various forms. Some information is stored in the structure of proteins that change shape and perform specific functions based on their amino acid sequences.
However, there are also: epigenetic influences such as chemical modifications to DNA and histone proteins; in the nervous system information is stored in the connections between neurons where synaptic strength and the pattern of connections between neurons store memories and learned behaviors; some organisms store information as behavioral patterns and learned experiences as they adapt both short- and long-term; social organisms convey information through vocalizations, chemical signals, body language and other means while social and intelligent animals like humans and dolphins use the cultural transmission of by traditions and learned behaviors and humans use recorded information as collective knowledge across generations; some cells in multicellular organisms retain memory of their specialized functions as a molecular and epigenetic profile retained through cellular differentiation; others store information about their environment and available resources through symbiotic relationships with other species such as mycorrhizal fungi that can store information about soil nutrients for plants.
Communication
A coordinated behavioral response requires the communication of information between all parts of the organism. In human terms, we can think of extremes such as, on the one hand, the unconscious internal signals needed to maintain and adjust the rhythm of our heartbeat and, on the other, the communication of information in the sounds of words exchanged between two people.
Electrical signals are transmitted along nerves byut there are many other modes of communication in the biological world.
the words human rain might be the most miraculous substance in the universe – matter that has become aware of itself – but the in-principle universal biological requirement of information is exactly the same for a plant as it is for a human. It is just that a brain achieves the same biological ends in a physically more complex way.
The fact that plants now make up over 80% of the Earth’s biomass indicates that they have been successful in achieving universal agential goals. This means that we have vastly underestimated the efficiency of plant communication systems. This would appear to be an open, exciting, and potentially highly productive field for biological research.
Of course, the genome is a vast repository of information storing the evolutionary history of each individual species right back to the origin of life. Plants and humans both use DNA and genes as ‘instructions’ for development, growth, and general functioning, the same essential mechanism used to translate the information stored in DNA into functional proteins, to control cell division, transcription (RNA synthesis), translation (protein synthesis), epigenetic modification, and metabolism. Many genes have homologous counterparts in both humans and plants and modes of genetic communication about basic biological functions are well-conserved across the tree of life.
Some aspects of this evolutionary agential homology are discussion in the article on plant intelligence.
Translation
When information is transferred it must be decoded and converted into an appropriate behavioral response.
Organisms use many ways to translate information the information that is used to coordinate their behavior including: chemical signals such as pheromones or hormones; visual Signals like body language, color changes, or displays; sound and vocalizations, notably frogs and birds; touch, as in grooming, nuzzling, and clinging plant tendrils; electrocommunication uses electric fields to communicate and navigate; mimicry in form, behavior, chemicals or other is used in many different ways; all organisms respond to environmental properties like temperature, humidity, or light; social hierarchies elicit relations of dominance and submission; genetic programming generates instinctual responses; learning and memory; cultural transmission through social learning; symbiotic relationships align behavior to benefit both parties. For example, cleaner fish provide cleaning services to larger fish in exchange for food.
Coordination
We humans have a strong sense that our destiny is a consequence of the rational consideration of our beliefs and desires all generated within our brains. Our brains are the control room for our bodies.
Evolutionary selection pressure has ensured that those organisms most effective at attaining agential goals have persisted. In animals, the coordination needed to achieve these goals involves the interaction of genetic factors (predispositions, instincts etc.), learned behaviors, the nervous system and brain, hormones, and environmental factors – essentially the integration sensory information, nervous system function, and physiological processes.
The complexity of the animal world (mostly a consequence of their mobility) does not overshadow their total dependence on plants which make up more than 80% of the world’s biomass. Plants too coordinate their growth, development, and reproduction with the aid of photoreceptors, hormones, chemicals, biological ‘clocks’, touch, and interaction with other organisms such as mycorrhizae and abiotic factors in their environment.
Principles of biological agency
This website has identified universal characteristics of biological agency. All organisms have the behavioral propensity to survive, reproduce, and flourish as ends that are demonstrated through the universal properties of information processing, behavioral orientation, and adaptation. These universal goals and properties are manifest in the infinite variety of individual structures, processes and behaviors that we see in the community of life, with each species demonstrating its universal properties in its own unique way.
Human agency is expressed through many unique properties of structure, process, and behavior, as they occur both singly and in combination. However, it is mindedness and conscious intention that is conventionally regarded as a defining feature of human agency.
We know that these uniquely minded characteristics must coexist with the universal characteristics shared by all living organisms, and out of which uniquely human features evolved.
The following list of words demonstrates how uniquely human cognitive states are connected to the universal conditions of biological agency. It first lists the uniquely human word meaning before its broader meaning, as it relates to biological agency, is provided in italics.
This illustrates well how the meanings of human cognitive terms can be extended into the realm of biological agency. How, for example, the word ‘purpose’ can vacillate between its uniquely human meaning and its more general application within biological agency.
Adaptation – for some reason we accept that plants can ‘adapt’ both short-term by responding to their conditions of existence, and long-term by genetic alteration. For example, in the short-term they respond to light direction and intensity in a way that maximizes sunlight absorption. This is driven by a genetic program, and not conscious understanding. These strategies could be thought of as a type of accumulated knowledge that has been encoded in their genetic makeup.
Agency – The human capacity to act in an autonomous way by, for example, making independent moral judgments. The exercise of autonomous goal-directed behavior.
Biological agency – The capacity to act on, and respond to the conditions of existence in an autonomous and flexible goal-directed way that expresses the universal, objective, and ultimate propensity to survive, reproduce, and flourish
Cognition – The human mental processes and activities related to acquiring, processing, storing, and using of knowledge. The processes and activities related to acquiring, processing, storing, and using of information by a biological agent.
Consciousness – The human awareness of immediate experiences. Also, the entire range of mental processes, including cognitive functions such as self-awareness, introspection, reasoning, memory, imagination, and the capacity for abstract thought. The totality of an individual’s subjective experiences and mental life. The capacity of a biological agent to orientate itself in relation to space, time, & its conditions of existence
Communication – The exchange of knowledge between humans by both verbal and non-verbal means. The exchange of information
Experience – event(s) that a human goes through or encounters, often characterized by being special in some way – by, say, uniqueness or personal involvement; sometimes the totality of life events, knowledge, emotions, and perceptions and overall comprehension and awareness of the world. The event(s) that a biological agent goes through or encounters in its umweldt including the way these are processed as information.
Human agency – A specialized form of biological agency that uses language and cognition.
Intelligence – The ability to acquire, understand and apply knowledge and reason to solve problems and adapt to new situations.
The capacity to acquire and process information that facilitates adaptation to the circumstances of existence and the attainment of goals.
Intention – The conscious attitude towards the effect of actions. Behavioral orientation
Knowledge – All forms of human awareness and comprehension of the world, including both subjective and objective aspects of our understanding. Information accumulated by an agent about its conditions of existence
Learning – The ability for personal growth and development through the processes of acquiring knowledge and skills. The capacity to process and accumulate information that may facilitate adaptation to the circumstances of existence and the attainment of goals.
Memory – The ability of the mind to store and recall information, experiences, and knowledge. The capacity for information storage and retrieval.
Perception – the human processing of sensory stimuli through the sensory system that includes the five traditional senses of sight, hearing, taste, smell, and touch, but sometimes including cognitive factors like mental processes, beliefs, desires, reason and their role in experience. The processing of the full range of experiential information (the umweldt) of a biological agent.
Reason – the mental faculty that enables individuals to think, analyze, and draw conclusions logically and rationally – to make sound judgments based on evidence and a structured thought process. The capacity to process information in a way that facilitates the attainment of goals.
Value – The word ‘value’ can be used as both a verb or a noun. When used in a human context it refers to the importance or significance attached to something based on emotional, objective or other factors. Values can include moral, ethical, cultural, and personal principles that guide behavior and decision-making. A behavioral propensity or disposition (towards).
Commentary
Agency in biology is most obviously demonstrated by autonomous organisms. We assess agency through the medium of behavior, and while the stimulus for behavior – the conditions of existence – might arise from inside or outside the organism, all behavior is the outcome of internal processing.
Since everything in the universe is connected, all explanations concerned with specific phenomena must entail simplification and reduction. One of the tasks of science is to provide the most economical but efficacious accounts of phenomena – the most obvious example being those equations of physics that can express universal phenomena in a few symbols. Perhaps biological agency will one day be expressed in a neat mathematical formula but, for the moment, a succinct verbal definition will have to do.
This website has identified a parsimonious and productive way to explain biological agency. conditions needed to explain biological agency. Biological explanations engage three key biological phenomena: structures, processes, and behaviors. In autonomous organisms it these three phenomena, in combination, that express universal, objective, and ultimate goals and conditions as a unity of purpose. These goals are manifested in the propensity to survive, reproduce, and flourish as a behavioral orientation entails information processing and adaptation.
That is, the community of life has evolved a wide range of structures, processes, and behaviors that engage information processing, and adaptation in a mindless behavioral propensity to survive, reproduce, and flourish. Humans and plants have each evolved their own individual and distinctive structures, processes, and behaviors to achieve the same ultimate goals by using the same ultimate means.
As humans, our natural inclination is to describe nature in human terms by using the language usually reserved for our uniquely human mental states. But it was nature that created humans through the process of evolution: humans did not create nature. The challenge, then, is not to look in nature for what is human but to understand what it is in organisms that made human subjectivity possible.
We are scientifically justified in speaking of biological agency because organisms, like all agents, are goal-directed. They act according to the universal, objective, and ultimate goals of survival, reproduction, and flourishing, these goals being our most parsimonious way of stating the necessary conditions for life. Importantly, these goals are not mysterious forces, they were not planted in organisms by God, they are not metaphorical creations of the human mind, and they do not exert a causal pull from the future – they are objective because they are empirically evident in the behavioral disposition of every organism in the present.
To attain these universal and objective goals certain preconditions must be met. While these (like the goals of life) may be expressed in various ways using various categories, they are most parsimoniously described here under the three categories of behavioral orientation, adaptation, and information processing, and referred to here as universal agential traits. Expressed in more general terms, the specific goals of biological agency give organisms a behavioral disposition or perspective on their existence. For these goals to be realized requires flexibility of behavior as the capacity to adapt to the circumstances of existence. To meet all conditions of life there must be communication of information in a manner that is not found in the inanimate world.
It is out of these universal agential traits that human agency – as minded (conscious) intentions – must have evolved.
In attempting to describe, as succinctly as possible, the features that most effectively describe our mental life, philosophers have identified three distinct mental realms: knowledge (epistemology), value (ethics), and reason (logic). From the time that this tripartite distinction was established, it has been found useful, suggesting that it is more than a convenient categorization; it corresponds to something real in our human nature.
From an evolutionary perspective, it is hardly surprising that there is a correspondence here between universal biological agential traits and the highly evolved human manifestation of these universal traits.
Information = knowledge
Behavioral disposition = value
Adaptation = reason (self-correction)
When we make the anthropomorphic statement, ‘That oak tree wants water’, instead of looking in nature for something uniquely human we can now look in nature for what it is that gave rise to this uniquely human sentiment.
An oak tree expresses reason, value, and knowledge in a crude and generalized form when compared to the highly evolved form in which they are found in humans. But these traits are nevertheless present in primordial (primitive, ancestral) form as universal and necessary agential conditions of life . . . a behavioral disposition, information processing, and adaptation.
Clearly, oak tree reason, value, and knowledge are vastly different from uniquely human reason, value, and knowledge. The point, however, is that there is a real-world evolutionary connection (not a metaphorical likeness) between the two.[7]
Organic complexity
The increase in complexity that we see in the organic world (especially that resulting from improved mobility and the advent of minds) is associated with an increase in the behavioural flexibility that marks individuality and independence.
The agential matter of living organisms expresses behavioural flexibility that is not present in the behaviourally constricted world of inorganic physics (see the biological axiom). And minded organisms demonstrate increasing degrees of behavioural freedom via an increasing capacity to learn, and which culminates in the flood of behavioural opportunities (degrees of behavioural freedom) made possible by human reason.
This may be seen as a process of increasing autonomy as, during evolution, individual organic agents became increasingly differentiated from their environments. Simple life which, in the early stages of evolution, was highly vulnerable to environmental influences, in the later stages gathered the organic complexity that allowed it to overcome, and even dominate, their environments.
This increase in behavioural freedom is amply demonstrated by humans as evolution’s greatest expression of individuality, acting collectively to disperse and dominate planet Earth in the Anthropocene.
Evolutionary increase in organic complexity is, in part, associated with an increase in individual behavioral freedom and independence. The behavioral flexibility of life over non-life is stated in the biological axiom, but further flexibility was added with the possibilities and opportunities opened up by the advent of mobility, the mind, learning, reason, language, and cooperation between individuals.
In general, the increasing autonomy of an organism (as it exists within the relationship of the organism-environment continuum) depends on its capacity to adapt – expressed as increasing behavioral flexibility.
Expressed in human-talk this relates to the organism’s accumulated ‘knowledge’, capacity to ‘learn’, and ‘innovate’ when confronted with novel circumstances. This is not, however, a recipe for evolutionary success since evolutionary diversification is subject to the path-dependent constraints of existing physical forms and environments. The apparent evolutionary success of highly autonomous and complex humans must be considered alongside the evolutionary success of insects, microbes, and plants.
The key characteristic of life lies not so much in the variety of its functions, processes, and material composition but that, collectively, these factors display a unity of purpose. Biologists, of necessity, investigate the parts of organisms in terms of their contribution to the integrity of the whole as a unified agent. In the absence of purpose and agency biology is just a collection of dissociated facts about the world with organisms treated in the same way that we treat inanimate matter.
Epilogue
The following list provides a condensed account of the key concepts discussed in the articles listed at the head of this article. See also the article called biological desiderata for a narrative account of these claims.
Biology
Biology is the study of life. The basic physical unit of life is the organism, whose basic unit of composition is the cell. The basic unit of biological classification is the species.
Life
Life is studied from many perspectives (physiological, thermodynamic, biochemical, genetic etc.) and on many scales (from molecules to populations and ecosystems etc.). From a human perspective, it is most easily comprehended in terms of autonomous organisms whose structures, processes, and behaviors are unified in the agential propensity to survive, reproduce, and flourish. It is this biological agency that most obviously distinguishes the living from the inanimate and dead.
Biological explanation
Biological explanations are grounded in two key ideas: the agential goal-directedness of autonomous organisms (the biological agency of Aristotelian teleology), and the temporal unity of the community of life due to its origin by natural selection from a common ancestor (Darwinian evolution).
Algorithm of life
Organisms are autonomous units of matter that self-replicate while incorporating feedback from the environment, thus enabling the possibility for individual change, but with a continuity of kind.
Organism
Is there empirical evidence for a preferred ranking of biological objects, or is this a subjective matter that depends on our individual interests and concerns? The interdependencies in biology are so strong that several candidates emerge as potential biological building blocks, the most notable being the cell, the gene, and the organism.
All organisms are composed of cells that have autonomy because they can perform the processes necessary for life, such as metabolism, reproduction, homeostasis, and the transmission of genetic information. Indeed, multicellularity probably evolved out of unicells by means of natural selection. Are cells the basic building blocks of life?
Genes play a crucial role in heredity and the functioning of cells, but they are not capable of independent existence.
It is the agential autonomy of organisms that stands out, even though they themselves have wider dependencies within more inclusive frames – populations of their own species within a wider environmental context.
It is the concentration of agency within readily identifiable physical units that is special and unique - their narrow agential ultimate focus on survival, reproduction, and flourishing. It is towards these goals that the structures, processes, and behavior of organisms are directed and therefore subordinated. This is what genes, cells, metabolism, growth, reproduction, and adaptation are ultimately for, and this is what singles out the organism as both an intuitive and natural autonomous category within the scheme of life.
The organism is the basic operational unit of biology, and therefore evolution, because it is the biological unit that displays most strongly the life-defining agential characteristics of the biological axiom – the universal, objective, and ultimate behavioral propensity to survive, reproduce, and flourish. Short-term behavioral goals drive organisms to adapt and compete in the immediate present while, over the long-term (many generations) this behavior results in the natural selection of genetic traits that are passed on to future generations.
The biological axiom
Living organisms are biological agents that express their autonomy as a unity of agency and purpose - the universal, objective, and ultimate behavioral propensity to survive, reproduce, and flourish when confronting their conditions of existence
The biological axiom observes that life is predicated on the survival, reproduction, and flourishing of organisms as autonomous agents.
This is a principle of life and its individuation. It states the necessary but conditional preconditions for life and how it is expressed through the integrated units of functional organization that we call organisms. As a statement of the objective goals of organisms it is a simple scientific statement of biological purpose.
Significantly, the goals of the biological axiom are mindless goals that are not the result of conscious deliberation; they are a precondition for life itself. Minds exist in bodies that are subordinate to bodily limitations and constraints.
The universal, objective, and ultimate goal-directed preconditions of the biological axiom are referred to here as biological agency. These goals are: universal because they are expressed by life as a whole; objective because they are a mind-independent empirical fact; and ultimate because they are a summation and unification of all proximate goals, including those of minded organisms. For the individual organism, these conditions are temporary because death is a precondition for individual lives, but its kind (the species) has the conditional potential to persist indefinitely.
The biological axiom is an existential grounding statement for all forms of biological agency including human minded agency - as well as purpose, intention, knowledge, reason, and value.
Biological goals
The fact that the behavior of biological agents is goal-directed does not mean that the goals themselves have causal efficacy, or that goals must entail conscious intentions. Goals are simply a behavioral orientation directed towards some outcomes rather than others. In human terms this is an expression of value that underpins, but does not determine, moral decisions.
Biological agency
Biological agency is an inherited life-defining property of living organisms that is expressed in autonomous behavior - the capacity of whole living organisms to act on, and respond to, their conditions of existence in a unified way. They do so in flexible ways that can potentially facilitate or impede (help or hinder) their existence. This flexible goal-directed behavior is grounded in the universal, ultimate, and objective goals of survival, reproduction, and flourishing (the biological axiom). These goals constitute a unity of purpose towards which all organisms - including their structures, processes, and behaviors - are directed.
Thus, living organisms are not passive, like rocks: they demonstrate behavioral autonomy that facilitates factors that promote these universal goals, and resist factors that impede them. Organisms therefore demonstrate behavior that resembles a human 'perspective', 'attitude', or 'point of view' in relation to their conditions of existence: they display objective behavior that mindlessly promotes their continued existence. This mindless behavioral orientation is a fact or mode of existence that in human terms would be interpreted as a value - 'it is better to live than not live'. This is a form of 'biological normativity' and it is reasonable to assume that it is out of this behavioral propensity that human values evolved, and in which human values are grounded.
It is the tension between the propensity to autonomy and the constraints of circumstance that establish the distinction between living agent and environment (expressed in human form as the distinction between 'self' and 'other').
The central importance of action in the expression of agency places emphasis on behavior directed towards goals or ends that are the starting point for biological explanation, these ultimate goals relating more to whole organisms as beneficiaries although supported by in the pursuit of these goals by the functioning of their parts, processes and behaviors. Even mindless living organisms have the capacity to discriminate between the objects and processes of their inner and outer environments,[50] adapting to circumstances with a goal-directed unity of purpose. The behavioral flexibility grounded in the objectives of the biological axiom, expresses the biological agency that is at the heart of biological science and its explanations of the natural world. It is out of this mindless behavioral flexibility and agential autonomy that our human subjectivity as a minded conscious capacity to discriminate between 'self' and 'other' evolved.
Parts of organisms do not have goals in the same way that autonomous organisms have goals. It is helpful to distinguish between the unity of purpose of an entire organism, to which its structures, processes, and behaviors contribute, and the functions of its parts. While functions can be independently interpreted and assessed, they are, nevertheless, subordinate to ultimate biological goals.
As open and dynamic agential systems, organisms regulate and integrate their flows of energy, materials, and information. In the short-term (one generation) this behaviour occurs over a lifecycle of fertilization, growth and development, maturation, reproduction, senescence, and death. Over the long term (multiple generations) organisms, as products of natural selection, display species-specific adaptive design and the potential to evolve new forms when heritable variation, transmitted to phenotypes via the chemical DNA, is subjected to environmental selection.
The emergent properties of biological agency arose in nature in a naturalistic and causally transparent way (inherited variation with feedback) that did not imply either backward causation or the intentions of either humans or gods. These agential, purposive, and normative properties of organisms preceded people in evolutionary time: they existed in nature mindlessly. That is, the notions of 'purpose', 'value', and 'agency' as described here, can refer to both minded and mind-independent conditions.
Agency has two key components: abstract goals that are expressed as a behavioral disposition, and the physical structures and processes that manifest these goals.
Agency & purpose
Goal-directed behavior is purposeful behavior - it is behavior for reasons or ends. The presence of goals need not imply the influence of God, the insinuation of human intent, or backward causation. Goal-directedness in nature is real, and without understanding the reasons for (purposes of) an organism's behavior as goals - including the role played by structures, processes, and behaviors in the attainment of these goals - biological explanation becomes an incoherent listing of dissociated facts.
Emphasis on ends may be interpreted as implying an unnatural backward causation or pull from the future. This is a quirk of explanation. Only when the ultimate goals expressed by the functional organization of a whole organism are appreciated can the roles of its necessitating parts and functions be fully understood. In this way biological ends have explanatory priority (hence the ‘final cause’ associated with teleology) but they do not challenge the natural order of cause and effect.
In a comparable way, the internal processing that initiates the behavior of organisms only becomes meaningful in terms of the behavior it generates. Behavior is explanatorily prior to the inner processing that initiates it (whether mental or other).
We ask about purposes and functions in biology precisely because organisms are agents. We do not ask what the moon or rocks are 'for', because they do not behave in a purposeful agential way.
Mindless biological purposes preceded, and gave rise to, the minded purposes we associate with human agency. That is, minded human agency evolved out of mindless biological agency. People did not create purpose and agency, it was the mindless purpose and agency in nature that gave rise to people - their bodies, brains, and minds.
The agential (goal-directed) orientation of biological behavior gives organisms a 'perspective' (albeit often a mindless one) on their existence such that their goals may be (mindlessly) helped or hindered.
Biological agency & human agency
Human minded agency evolved out of the mindless biological agency whose ultimate goals (behavioral propensities) were established billions of years before.
Biological agency and human agency are not mutually exclusive characteristics in the same way that we might regard organisms with minds as distinct from those without minds. That is, while human agency has uniquely minded characteristics it also shares the universal grounding characteristics of biological agency.
This may be compared to the way we accept that sexuality exists (almost) universally across the community of life, even though it is expressed in a wide range of behaviors and physical forms. Human sexuality is expressed in a uniquely human way, but this does not mean that only human sexuality is 'real', and that the sexuality of other organisms is only sexual-like.
Adaptation
The word ‘adaptation’ is used as both a verb denoting process (an organism adapting to its environment) and a noun (the eye is a complex adaptation). It is the latter that is generally applied in formal definitions such as 'an evolved phenotypic trait that enhances fitness'.
The process of adaptation has both short- and long-term components that are both determined by the ultimate goals of the biological axiom.
Short-term adaptation is behavioral adaptation; it is the compromise reached between the ultimate demands of the biological axiom and its conditions of existence. This is a real-time fine-tuning of behavior as an expression of organismal autonomy and is presumably what Darwin meant when he talked about the ‘struggle for life’. This struggle, over the long term, results inherited novelties as genetic adaptation resulting in evolutionary change. Over many generations, changes in structures, processes, or behaviors that enhance an organism's differential survival and reproduction based on their heritable traits (fitness maximization) are referred to as adaptations. It is a form of phenotypic control that occurs throughout the biological system but is expressed most obviously in the integrated goals of autonomous organisms. Behavioral adaptation, over the longer term, determines the heritable traits of structures, processes, or behaviors that affect an organism's survival and reproduction, and it is these heritable traits, that are called adaptations and are treated as being at the core of fitness maximization. In short, organisms are the canonical units enacting evolutionary change, even when change is expressed in non-organismal terms, such as the properties of genes.
Conditions of existence can facilitate or impede the attainment of behavioral goals, a consequence of the universal organismal behavioral orientation (biological axiom). As a biological agent, then, goals may be 'helped' or 'hindered' giving organisms a behavioral 'perspective' on life as a 'mindless value'. If desired, the implication of agency is avoided by either describing agential traits as dispositional properties or as etiological outcomes (an inevitable developmental or evolutionary outcome).
While not all traits are necessarily adaptive, or an outcome of natural selection (there may be other evolutionary processes involved) Darwin’s key concept of natural selection acting on heritable variation within a population remains the cornerstone of empirically based evolutionary theory.
Biological agency is a grounding notion for both single- and multiple-generation change. The language of adaptation, natural selection, selective pressure, fitness maximization, and evolution in general, are littered with words like ‘better’ and ‘worse’, ‘help’ and ‘hinder’, facilitate’ or ‘impede’, ‘benefits’ and ‘disadvantages’, 'strategies', and so on. The inappropriate use of anthropomorphism is an attempt to express the real but mindless biological agency that is still not fully acknowledged in biological science. While adaptation, like the behavior of most organisms, is neither deliberate nor conscious it is, nevertheless, the product of agential (goal-directed) behavior: that is, the notion of adaptation brings with it, of necessity, the notion of agency. The notion of fitness associated with adaptation is blatantly and inherently agential in character. Without the presumption of agency, the concepts of adaptation and natural selection are, to all intents and purposes, incoherent.
Aristotle gave Darwin the agential key that was needed to unlock the theory of evolution.
Proximate & ultimate goals
The multitude of operations/functions of structures, processes, and behaviors of organisms are all subordinate (proximate to) the ultimate and mindless goals of the biological axiom.
Human minded goals are, in this sense, only proximate goals that serve the whole-body ultimate and mindless goals of biological agency that had evolved billions of years before.
So, for example, we humans eat for minded proximate ends (taste and smell stimulation and the satiation of hunger), that have the mindless ultimate biological end of survival. We have sex for minded proximate ends (orgasm, physical and emotional gratification), but also for the mindless ultimate biological end of reproduction. We develop moral and political systems seeking the minded proximate ends of happiness, wellbeing, and pleasure, while serving the ultimate and mindless biological end of flourishing.
Physical & conceptual gradation
Before Darwin each species was regarded as a unique creation of God. Human bodies were the repositories of everlasting souls with the mind a special domain of religious and philosophical investigation. After Darwin (mid-19th century) the entire community of life was viewed as a graded continuum of organic kinds with the human brain and mind bodily elements open to scientific investigation. Harking back to this transition, it remains unclear whether some concepts relate strictly and exclusively to human minds and human agency or whether they share more generalized features with biological agency and the continuum of life.
Consider the sentence -
'The design we see in nature is only apparent design'.
We say that design in nature is ‘apparent’ (not real) because it is not human design, it is not created by human minds. But nature and organisms are replete with real designed structures in patterns more complex, beautiful, and ordered than anything created by humans. Mindless nature ‘created’ the miraculous and intricately integrated human body, including the brain that provides us with conscious representations of nature’s real design.
The problem is that, for many people, ‘design’ (and other words like ‘purpose’, ‘reason’, ‘knowledge’ and ‘value’) are strictly minded words appropriate only in the context of the human mind. Thus, the word ‘design’ is only used nervously in relation to organisms because it seems to imply that either mindless organisms have minds, or they were created by God. We overcome this semantic confusion with verbal obfuscation. We say that nature is 'design-like' or 'designoid'.
But the implication that without minds design is not possible is clearly, and obviously, mistaken.
Our anthropocentrism simply refuses to countenance the possibility of mindless design. We forget that in biology it is the mindless goals of the biological axiom that take precedence over their later evolutionary development, the intentions of the human mind, and that they can exist in nature in a graded way. Following philosopher Dan Dennett's mode of expression, we forget that . . . 'purpose’, ‘reason’, 'agency', ‘knowledge’, ‘value’, 'design' and many other concepts often attributed strictly to human minds (like consciousness) emerged out of the evolutionary process by degree: they 'bubbled up from the bottom, not trickled down from the top'.
Biological agency is not a fiction of the human mind, it 'created' human agency. Many of the concepts related strictly to human agency are best considered scientifically as sharing properties with biological agency and, in this sense, of existing in nature by degree.
Biological normativity
The biological axiom is simultaneously a statement of biological agency, biological purpose, and biological normativity. The normativity exists as a mindless perspective on existence expressed as a behavioral orientation that can be helped or hindered by circumstance. This is 'normative' behavior because as biological agents, organisms are not passive, they express 'preferences', and 'choices', albeit mindless ones.
As a statement of biological normativity the biological axiom expresses the objective, universal, and ultimate behavioural
orientation of all living organisms towards survival, reproduction, and flourishing over multiple generations. This behavioural orientation resembles a set of generalized and mindless rules for living, like a human code of conduct, and since these goals were the evolutionary precursors to human behavioral codes, they are appropriately referred to as biological normativity. But, as a mindless form of normativity, these biological values are not recommendations for behavior, or judgements about behavior, they are objective statements about the way organisms are.
Biological values are manifest differently in each biological agent. The physical structures, processes, and behaviors adopted by a spider to obtain its life energy, produce offspring, and flourish are very different from those of a sea urchin, eucalyptus tree, or the minded and proximate values of humans.
The mindless behaviour of the biological axiom is like (because evolutionarily related to) a human perspective or point of view. But the likeness is not the ‘as if’ similarity of metaphor but the reality of an evolutionary connection that warrants scientific recognition, since it is out of mindless biological values that human minded values evolved. This was the evolutionary precursor to human proximate minded goals that arise as both organismal biological desires and the culturally reasoned beliefs and codes that result from a critical examination of behavioural consequences. It is also why ultimate and objective biological goals can be expressed in human proximate subjective terms as the behavioural flexibility that allows organisms to exercise choices in relation to their interests.
Biological normativity and human normativity are not mutually exclusive. In behavioural terms, biological normativity is the lived expression of both unconscious (mindless) and conscious (minded) goals, where these occur. In humans they have taken on a highly evolved and minded form that includes reason.
Ethics (moral naturalism)
We often assume that judgements about what can 'help' or 'hinder' our lives, what makes a situation 'better' or 'worse', what is 'right' and 'wrong', 'good' and 'bad', are part of a human domain of subjective normative assessment that has little, if anything, to do with nature. How could it be otherwise? After all, nature itself does not think, it just is. Nature does not make moral decisions, or recommend codes of behaviour - that is nonsense. Moralities are obviously creations of human subjective deliberation, the application of what we call 'reason' as found only in human minds.
But . . .
We have inherited from nature a legacy of biological normativity as a behavioural orientation (a mindless 'code of conduct') - the behavioural goals of the biological axiom. When human minds evolved, along with their uniquely conscious and reasoning subjectivity, this universal, objective, and ultimate biological behavioural orientation was manifested in proximate minded form - in part as organismal needs, desires and intuitions, but also in part as cultural moral, and other, codes of behaviour - still grounded in ultimate biological normativity, but fine-tuned by reason. Moralities are human creations, but they are grounded in natural facts.
Aristotle's normative imperative
Biological agency expresses the 'values' (the quotes indicate an objective behavioural orientation) of survival, reproduction, and flourishing as a necessary condition for life. This is what it means to be a living organism - it is a biological necessity.
Aristotle maintained that the ultimate goals of biological agency drive us to the conclusion that – ‘It is better to exist than not exist‘, and ‘it is better to live than not live’ – referred to here as Aristotle’s biological normative imperative. Humans describe such statements as subjective value judgements that have no logical necessity. But as statements expressing the objective nature of all organisms, including humans, (but not in inanimate objects) they do express biological necessity.
Why do organisms have the propensity to survive, reproduce, and flourish? . . . ‘Because natural selection made them so‘ (Armand Leroi[40]). Critically, and in apparent contradiction, this is not what organisms need to do, or ought to do (human subjective minded values); it is the way that they are (objective biological 'values'). It is out of these mindless values that evolution forged minded values.
Aristotle's normative imperative - the propensity of life, both individuals and kinds, to resist death - is an objective fact: it is not the projection of human subjective values onto life. Humans may make the minded and contestable value judgement, that 'it is good to live', but mindless organisms do not make value judgments, their biological 'normativity' is expressed in the way that they are. But humans, since they express both mindless biological agency (objective behavioural orientation) and minded human agency (subjective value) thus express both fact and value simultaneously (cf. the philosophical distinction between fact and value).
Fact & value
Our anthropocentric emphasis on the uniquely human trait of mindedness has contributed to an artificial intellectual gulf between humans and other organisms that has diminished the significance of our real biological connection. This can be attributed, in part, to the anthropocentric elevation of mindedness into a realm of values as a special mental and linguistic domain that stands in stark contrast to an unconnected realm of discourse that we call facts.
This putative difference between facts and values is widely respected within the scientific and philosophical communities. It not only sets humans apart from nature, it also separates ethics from science, and science from the humanities. But it has always been a topic of philosophical contention.
The distinction between facts and values can be addressed from the perspective of evolutionary biology.
Let us assume, reasonably, that human minded agency and its subjective values evolved out of the objective goals of the biological axiom. One simple answer to a question about the way this occurred is to say that human values arrived with human brains, thus reinforcing the fact-value distinction.
A more thorough answer would point out that both our values and ethical decisions are derived in a complex way that has both minded and mindless ingredients. Both biological and human values are established primarily through behaviour with human mindless (unconscious) behaviour including physiological responses (sweating, digesting) as well as impulses, instincts, intuitions, and other unconscious drivers emanating from the evolutionarily earlier structures of the brain. These sources are, in effect, the objective remnants of our biological agency still exerting an objective (unconscious) influence on our values, including our ethical decisions. However, human conscious values communicated by language include both unconscious and conscious elements that are moderated by our reasoning which occurs in the most recently evolved part of our brain, the frontal cortex.
We respect reason, in part, because it can substantially, but not wholly, override the influences of our mindless and unconscious biological agency.
But when we understand our subjective values from this perspective we see that they are a mixture of our inherited ancient and objective biological values (the mindless and unconscious influences on our behaviour) and the application of reason to our knowledge of these and other factors. What we call our subjective values as established by reason, include an admixture of varying quantities of objective biological value depending on circumstance. Our biology has inseparably entangled both fact and value.
Such a proposal triggers a cognitive dissonance because we both confuse (fail to distinguish between) and conflate (treat as being identical) the universal, objective, and ultimate facts of biological agency, and the uniquely human values of human agency. We fail to realize that it is possible for values to simultaneously express both similarity and difference: the shared features of biological normativity and the unique features of human agency including the use of reason with other advanced cognitive faculties.
We all (but especially intellectuals and ethicists) like to think of morality as demonstrating the supremacy of reason (morality established by pure reason), but our inclination (necessarily locked into our reason) in both politics and ethics, is to fall back on the proximate human values of maximizing happiness, wellbeing, and pleasure as influenced by the ultimate biological value of flourishing.
Biological normativity is not prescriptive in the way that moral language is prescriptive. But the faculty of reason that we proudly and rightly regard as a uniquely distinguishing feature of human agency is still grounded in biological agency and biological normativity. Though reason attempts to transcend, overcome, or be detached from biological normativity, it can only ever be partially successful. Reason itself is, of evolutionary necessity, still ultimately grounded in the biological values that give it purchase. The moral decisions that we think overcome biological normativity simply fall back on second order biological normativity.
We can and do override our biological impulses with our ethical systems (Thou shalt not kill) but the reasons I observe this moral injunction still derived from my biological normativity. Without its foundation in biological normativity, the use of reason in moral decision-making is an incoherent and empty concept.
Since reason can never fully extricate itself from biological normativity, we must face the fact that moral discourse reduces to biological facts, that human proximate and subjective valuing evolved out of ultimate and objective biological facts. The differentiation of facts and values, the descriptive and prescriptive is, at least, exaggerated. Organisms have biological values in human-like way because that is the way they (objectively) are, and that is what led to our own subjective values.
The acceptance of the reality of biological values provides us with a more compelling scientific account of nature since the assimilation of human values to biological values acknowledges the uniquely mindful properties of human values while at the same time recognizing that they evolved out of, and share major characteristics with, their mindless evolutionary antecedents.
Technical language
We humans describe our own form of agency using the minded vocabulary of intentional psychology (needs, wants, desires, beliefs, preferences etc.) This is, in effect, a set of technical terms for the uniquely minded agency manifested by Homo sapiens.
Since the species Homo sapiens has its own agential vocabulary, a thoroughly objective science would develop parallel vocabularies for the unique modes of agency expressed by every other individual species – an impossible task. This is one major reason why we fall back on the use of human-talk as cognitive metaphor - simply because it is the agential language that is most familiar to us.
It is tempting to create a vocabulary of technical terms expressing, on the one hand, biological agency and, on the other, human agency, but this would be speciesism in the extreme.
But there is a further difficulty because, as already pointed out, biological agency and human agency are not mutually exclusive concepts. The proximate and uniquely minded goals of human agency evolved out of, and share characteristics with, the universal, objective, and ultimate mindless goals of biological agency.
Mindedness is not a precondition for agency in living organisms: mindedness is simply one expression of biological agency. We conflate the simple distinction between the minded and the mindless with the complex distinction between biological agency and human agency. It is not that biological agency is a subjective creation of the human mind (cognitive metaphor or heuristic), rather that the proximate and uniquely minded goals of human agency evolved out of, and share characteristics with, the universal, objective, and ultimate mindless goals of biological agency. More simply, the objective behavioural orientation of mindless organisms (mindless purpose) created minds: minds did not create purpose.
There is only one possible scientific solution - an acknowledgement that if current linguistic usage is to reflect nature, then minded concepts like 'agent', 'knowledge', 'reason', 'preference', and 'value', which are currently restricted to discourse about humans, are extended into the realm of mindless agency. This also means that what is currently regarded as metaphor is more aptly treated in literary terms (assuming literary analagies are appropriate here) as simile (see 'metaphor fallacy' below).
Anthropomorphism (human-talk)
We frequently apply to non-human organisms the language that is usually preserved for humans. This is known as anthropomorphism but is referred to here, more simply, as human-talk.
We use human-talk for many reasons including: literary flourish; brevity; our human cognitive bias; and as an educational heuristic - because they make biological explanations simpler and easier to understand.
One special form of human-talk occurs when we use the language of human intentional psychology to describe non-human organisms. This is generally referred to as cognitive metaphor.
Cognitive metaphor
Cognitive metaphor is a clumsy way of acknowledging the mindless, but real, goal-directed behavior (biological agency) that is a defining characteristic of all living organisms. This use of minded language in relation to mindless organisms is one particular kind of anthropomorphism. Scientifically, this is unacceptable because it gifts organisms with cognitive qualities that, in reality, they do not, and cannot, possess.
We humans have emphasized our uniquely human kind of agency by developing a uniquely minded vocabulary (we speak of needs, wants, desires, beliefs, preferences etc.) that expresses conscious intentions, sometimes called the language of intentional psychology. A thoroughly objective science would develop parallel vocabularies to describe the unique agencies of every species – an impossible task.
However, in many cases of so-called cognitive metaphor, the language is clearly intended to convey the biological likeness associated with the grounding characteristics of biological agency, not inferring that the organism has cognitive faculties. In other words, anthropomorphic language interpreted, not literally, but in terms of its intended meaning, describes a relationship between humans and non-humans that is a real likeness based on descent with modification (biological simile grounded in evolution) not cognitive metaphor grounded in a literary device. It expresses a meeting of shared biological agency, not a meeting of minds.
We say that a plant needs water, not because we think that plants experience cognitive states (human agency), but because we intuitively appreciate the significance of survival for all life (biological agency). It is not as if a plant wants water, rather, in terms of the biological agency that plants share with humans they depend on water for their survival. The agency being communicated here is not as if or even like, but the same as our human biological dependency on water. In this sense a plant needs water for exactly the same reasons that humans need water.
We say the purpose of eyes is to see, not because eyes were an intentional creation of God, or that their purpose is a projection of our own intentions, but because, from the perspective of biological agency (the objective behavioural orientation of all organisms) we understand the agential significance of sight for all organisms that have eyes. It is not as if the purpose of eyes is to see but, conversely, given the nature of biological agency, eyes have obvious and objective agential significance.
We say a spider knows how to build its web, not because we believe that spiders are consciously aware of the principles of web construction, but because we are amazed at how, without our cognitive powers, spiders instinctively build something as intricate and purposeful as a web, using information that is passed mechanically, and with meticulous precision, from one generation to the next in their genes. Even though the capacity for web building is an adaptive trait encoded in genes, rather than a cognitive attribute, it is a manifestation of biological agency that is so sophisticated that we rightly associate it with our own agency. It is not as if a spider knows how to build a web, rather, that web building (biological agency) is extraordinarily like (and biologically related to) our human cognitive capacity to learn, remember, and apply accumulated knowledge (human agency).
Minds, bodies, & behavior
The internal processes of organisms are of biological significance only in so far as they influence behaviour: it is behaviour that confronts the testing arena of the environment.
From a human perspective this is not immediately obvious because our human conscious intentions are vivid and, even though these intentions are private, we see obvious causal connections between our intentions and outcomes in the world. There is, however, an existential directness about behaviour. We are not committed to jail for what we think, but for what we do (how we behave): it is actions and deeds (agency, behaviour) that speak louder than words. Words and ideas can indeed change the world, but only through the medium of behaviour.
A subtle shift in semantic focus takes place when talk moves from mental states to bodily behaviour, from brains with intentions to bodies with goals. First, it draws attention to the fact that human agency as expressed by human bodies engages not only our conscious intentions, but also factors determined by bodily and unconscious needs. Second, the emphasis on behaviour draws attention away from uniquely minded human agency and towards the universal goal-directed activity of all organisms as a life-defining characteristic, and an objective fact.
If we want to understand the biological significance of human agency then we must look to human behaviour and in so doing we must also look to those aspects of human behaviour that, as a consequence of evolution, are held in common with other organisms – the mutual connections that exist between human agency and biological agency.
The denial of biological agency, purpose, and values
Scour biological textbooks, or the web, and you will find little, if anything, about biological agency, biological values, or the purpose that pervades everything in nature.
This downplaying of biological agency probably dates from a time before evolutionary theory, when each species was considered a unique and special creation of God with humans being special ‘ensouled’ beings distinct from all the other creatures that had been placed on earth for human benefit.
The denial of real biological agency, purpose, and value rests on several interrelated confusions concerning the distinction between, on the one hand, organisms with minds and those without minds and, on the other, biological agency and human agency.
First, an inversion of reasoning.
In biology it is the agential behaviour of autonomous bodies that most directly determines outcomes, regardless of the internal processes that influence this behaviour. So, for example, human agency is most potently expressed by actions, not thoughts and words. Words and ideas can indeed change the world, but only through the medium of behaviour.
Because the purposes and values inherent in biological agency can only be understood by (represented in) human minds, it is often assumed that they can only exist in human minds – that they are therefore a creation of human minds. From this error of reasoning, it follows that only humans can be agents with goals, purposes, and values: that non-human organisms are, at best, only agent-like. Whereas, in fact, rather than biological goals being an invention of human minds, they are the biological substrate out of which the goals of human agency evolved.
Certainly, only minded humans can understand why animals have eyes, fish have fins, and cacti have spines; but this does not mean that these reasons and purposes do not exist outside human minds. Of course, the purpose of a prosthetic leg is established by the intentions of its inventor, but legs that occur in nature likewise have purposes, even though they were created by a natural process with no conscious intentions. We mistakenly conflate a lack of conscious intention with a lack of agency. Simply because non-human organisms lack self-awareness, does not mean that they also lack agency – that agency is mind-dependent.
Biological goals can only be understood (represented by) human minds, but that does not mean that they only exist in human minds – that they are a creation of human minds. The goals of non-human organisms are not spoken or thought; they are demonstrated in their behaviour, and they existed (were real) in nature long before they made possible the evolution of human brains, minds, and language.
Second, converse reasoning.
The pre-Darwinian mental representation of the world as a Great Chain of being (Ladder of Life) placed humans in an exalted position just below God.
Darwin replaced the image of the ladder with that of a tree whose branches were constrained by what had gone before. Humans were just one of the many evolutionary outcomes of the interaction between autonomous organisms and their ancestral environments.
Agency in nature has, likewise, taken on as many different forms as there are species, each species expressing its agency in its own way as constrained by its physical form. We marvel at the internal processing agency of the human intellect while ignoring, say, the mental miracle of a bat catching a fly using echolocation inside a cave teeming with other bats.
At present our inherited pre-Darwinian intellectual tradition treats human agency as the only real agency with biological agency its unreal (as if) creation – the reading of human agency into non-human mindless organisms.
Scientifically the converse applies. Human agency has its origin in the biological agency that made human subjectivity possible. Human agency (for all its conscious, deliberative, and abstractive brilliance) is just one of many forms of biological agency and must be scientifically explained in terms of the evolutionary context out of which it arose.
Biological agency is not a fiction invented by the human consciously agential mind. The converse applies. Human agency is just one highly evolved example of the many kinds of biological agency that made human subjectivity possible.
Third, the metaphor fallacy.
The treatment of minded humanizing language as cognitive metaphor.[42] This fallacy interprets the relationship between biological agency and human agency using the logic of a literary device, the metaphor, in which one of the relata is always figurative (unreal). This forces the real evolutionary likeness between biological agency and human agency to be treated as an 'as if' (unreal) likeness, rather than a similarity resulting from real evolutionary connection. Were a literary device the appropriate mechanism for making this comparison then, in strict literary terms, the likeness is not metaphor but simile.
Fourth, the the agency error.
In science and philosophy, it is conventional for the anthropomorphic language of human intentional psychology (wants, needs, knows, deceives etc.), as applied to non-human organisms, to be treated as cognitive metaphor since it erroneously implies that mindless organisms possess cognitive faculties. By extension we then assume that non-human organisms therefore have no purpose and no agency.
There is a major flaw in this conventional account of cognitive metaphor. Subsuming all agency under human agency deprives mindless organisms of any form of agency. It refuses to acknowledge both the real and universal character of biological agency that unites the community of life, and its behavioral expression through evolutionarily graded forms.
Under closer inspection it is evident that, in general, such language is not referencing a figurative likeness based on human intentions (metaphor) but a real likeness (simile) that is grounded in universal biological agency, the goals of the biological axiom. For example, we say that a plant ‘wants’ water, not because we believe that plants have human-like desires, but because we acknowledge the universal disposition of all living organisms to survive, reproduce, and flourish.
We confuse the distinction that exists between the universal biological agency shared by all organisms and the minded form of this agency that is uniquely human. Much of the intentional language of human-talk applied to mindless organisms references universal biological, not uniquely human, agency.
This is the traditional and mistaken assumption that the agency we imply when using anthropomorphic language is the unique agency of humans when, in fact, its intended meaning relates to the universal biological agency that is present in all living organisms.
When we say that a plant ‘wants’ or ‘needs’ water we are not suggesting that plants experience intentional mental states, but that they share with us the universal biological agential disposition to survive, reproduce, and flourish. This is a form of biological empathy - but not a communion of minds, more a recognition of shared and mindless biological values.
Biological agency is not a metaphorical creation of human agency: human agency is a real evolutionary development of biological agency.
Fifth, biological empathy.
In spite of attempts to rid biology of purpose, agency, cognitive metaphor and other forms of the teleological idiom, we continue to use these forms of language because we fail to recognize that in doing so we are acknowledging the universal goals of biological agency, not the uniquely intentional goals of human agency.
For this reason - which amounts to a human empathy with biological agency - biology will never rid itself of teleology because this is a teleology that is grounded in the reality of evolutionary connection.
Sixth Precedence of behaviour over minds
Agency is expressed by the behavior of the bodies of autonomous agents. It is behavior as action (regardless of the internal process generating that behaviour) that most directly determines biological outcomes. Conscious intentions are uniquely human, but behaviour grounded in the biological axiom is expressed by all organisms and it takes explanatory precedence over internal causation. Human behaviour, as influenced by conscious intentions, evolved out of mindless biological goals and is just one form of biological agency.
Seventh, Anthropocentric agential language
As uniquely minded organisms we humans we have devised the language of intentional psychology to describe our species-specific minded agency. Since there are no equivalent vocabularies for other species it is unsurprising that we use our own minded Homo sapiens terms to describe the agency of other organisms.
Anthropomorphic analogical language is, in general, not trying to convey the as if language of cognitive metaphor, but the real likeness of biological simile (the result of evolutionary connection).
From an evolutionary perspective human agency evolved out of (is a subset of) biological agency and thus the proximate minded and therefore (often) subjective goals of human agency, are subordinate to the ultimate objective goals of biological agency.
In sum, we have yet to scientifically accept that biological agency is not a metaphorical creation of human agency: human agency is a real evolutionary development of biological agency.
Historically, this philosophical confusion has been perpetuated by a pre-Darwinian anthropocentrism that understood life as Special Creation, rather than evolution with modification from a common ancestor.
If we regard anthropomorphism as cognitive metaphor or heuristic, then we not only devalue, but deny, the real evolutionarily graded agential reality of the organisms, structures, processes, and behaviours that unite the community of life.
If biological agency, goals, purposes, and values are real then their investigation can be transferred out of the realm of philosophical speculation and into the domain of scientific explanation.
Forms of biological agency
For humans, autonomy entails a conscious distinction between ‘self’ and ‘other’. Our minds provide a sense of self as they segregate the world into objects of experience, focus on a limited range of these, group them according to similarities and differences, and prioritize them according to purpose, interest, or preparation for action. For simplicity we can refer to this complex agential process as mental adaptation, which is a form of human agency.
This minded human agency evolved out of the capacity of mindless organisms (as revealed by their behaviour) to discriminate between objects of their environment and to prioritize these in relation to themselves and their behaviour. That mindless adaptation is a demonstration of both autonomy and agency. And it is clearly out of this mindless process of adaptation that minded adaptation evolved.
Biological agency is manifest through agential behaviour as expressed by each biological body. This behaviour is relatively uniform within a species due to their similarity of physical form. The agency of a plant is expressed in very different ways from from that of a fish. However, since all organisms arose from a common ancestor the agential similarities between organisms is always a matter of degree.
When considering agency as it relates to minds, five kinds can be distinguished each building on the former:
mindless inorganic 'agency' - the ordering 'behaviour' of inanimate matter
mindless biological agency - agential (goal-directed) behaviour that is not mind-directed (also found in minded organisms e.g. unconscious sweating)
unconscious minded agency - the unconscious, intuitive or instinctive behaviour of minded creatures e.g. fear of snakes
conscious minded agency - as behaviour that is a consequence of conscious deliberation
collective or cultural agency - behaviour that is a product of collective learning usually communicated through symbolic language as socio-cultural norms
First published on the internet – 1 March 2019
. . . 24 September 2023 – revision including evolutionary connections between biological and human agencies
. . . 26 September 2023 – ongoing revision
Biological Revolution
Theoretical biology is currently experiencing a paradigm shift in its foundational ideas as the concepts of agency and cognition are extended beyond the human (sentient) domain to non-human organisms.
Biological agency is evident in the universal capacity of organisms to act on and respond to their conditions of existence in flexible and goal-directed ways as they survive, reproduce, adapt, and evolve. These universal characteristics distinguish life from non-life and are found in both the simplest and most complex organisms.
Biological cognition is a universal property of biological agents that has a real functional equivalence to human cognition. It considers how organisms access, store, retrieve, process, prioritize, and communicate information; how they and their parts use various forms of reasoning or problem-solving. Collectively, these properties provide the adaptive functionality that integrates organismal proximate and ultimate goals and distinguishes organisms as the primary autonomous biological agents. It includes equivalences of reason, value, knowledge, memory, learning, communication, perception, experience, sentience, even subjectivity, and more. Biological perception, for example, refers to the way organisms adaptively interpret and prioritize sensory data, allowing them to perceive and respond to their conditions of existence.
Biological agency and biological cognition were the functional evolutionary precursors to human agency and human cognition, so we often describe them using the language of human cognition and intentional psychology. Mistakingly treating these traits in non-human organisms as imaginary (cognitive metaphors ) ignores the fact that they are manifest in organisms as real functional adaptations expressed in evolutionarily graded physical form.
Human agency and human cognition are thus understood as anthropocentric notions that describe highly evolved, and limited human forms of universal biological agency and biological cognition.
These philosophical changes are part of the framework of the Extended Evolutionary Synthesis (EES) which expands on traditional evolutionary theory by incorporating new insights from developmental biology, epigenetics, and ecology, notably the acknowledgment of organisms as active participants in their own evolution, shaping their own developmental trajectories and those of their descendants.
This re-evaluation of the human relationship to other species represents a significant expansion of human knowledge. It opens new research fields, challenges the foundations of theoretical biology, and has ethical implications for the way we interact with other living beings.
What is life?
The biological axiom
The basic unit of biological classification, ecology, and evolution (and therefore life) is the organism. But what is it that distinguishes the life of organisms from the inanimate and the dead? Organisms possess many structures (e.g. genes, cells), processes (e.g. metabolism, homeostasis), and behaviors (e.g. response to stimuli) that are necessary for life: but are any of these specially defining in some way?
Aristotle noted that to continue existing (to survive by perpetuating their kind) living beings must reproduce. He said that all living creatures ‘partake in the eternal and divine’. By this, he meant that organisms can potentially replicate their kind (species) indefinitely (eternally) provided they can survive. Biologists have subsequently regarded survival and reproduction, more than any other properties, as crucial characteristics of life.
Darwin, like Aristotle, acknowledged that organisms are not passive: they act on and respond to their conditions in a 'struggle for existence'. This interaction between the organism and its conditions of existence is a process of adaptation. Adaptation is currently strongly associated with long-term genetic change in populations. However, this long-term genetic change begins with short-term behavioral adjustment to immediate conditions. Short- and long-term adaptation results in organisms that are the products of agential self-determination. It is the agency of organisms (loosely equivalent to Aristorle's telos) - as objectively demonstrated by the myriad structures, processes, and behaviors of the community of life - that provides the motivation or drive - the vitality - that distinguishes the living from the dead.
These, then, are the key ingredients for a modern definition of life as an agential process:
Life is typically exemplified by the autonomous agency of living organisms whose structures, processes, and behaviors express a functionally integrated unity of purpose – the universal, objective, and ultimate propensity to survive, reproduce, adapt, and evolve. These goals are universal because they are a necessary precondition for life itself, objective because they are a mind-independent fact, and ultimate because they are a summation of all proximate goals. These are thus the defining conditions of biological agency and the natural limits or ends of the biological conditions that define both life and evolution, driving the continuous development and diversification of life. They provide a comprehensive framework for understanding the mechanisms of evolution and the dynamic nature of life on Earth.
0 Comments